(This is a guest post I was invited to write for the atheist blog Deity Schmeity. Regular readers of Armarium Magnum or of my answers on Quora will recognise the general themes).
"History sucks."
In April last year Grundy, the usual writer of this blog,
posted "History Isn't My Area", commenting on the release of Bart
Ehrman's critique of the Jesus Myth hypothesis, Did Jesus Exist?: The Historical Argument for Jesus of Nazareth. Unlike the majority of actual historians,
many prominent atheists find Jesus Mythicism convincing and many of them are
unhappy with the generally sceptical and highly renowned Ehrman for criticising
this idea. Grundy, for his part, stated
frankly "I honestly have little knowledge as to whether or not Jesus
existed", though added "I tend
to think he did". That said, he
made it clear why the overwhelming consensus of historians and other relevant
scholars that the Jesus Myth idea is junk was underwhelming for him:
"History sucks. Okay,
that’s unfair, but it was never my subject. My confidence of the accuracy of
historical events goes down exponentially with the paper trail. The idea that
history is written by the victors highlights the biases of the past. Books are
burned. Records fade. Who should I trust for an accurate portrayal of events
two thousand years ago?"
Since history actually is my area, I responded by
making some critical comments on this attitude and some points about how
history , as an academic discipline, is studied. Grundy, unlike many so-called
"rationalists" I've encountered over the years, was happy to listen,
and he invited me to expand on my points in this guest post.
Atheists and Historical Illiteracy
I should begin, however, by pointing out that I am an
atheist. I have been an atheist for my
entire adult life, am a paid up member of several atheist and sceptical
organisations and have a 21 year online record of posting to discussions as an
unbeliever. I note this because I've
found that when I begin to criticise my fellow atheists and their grasp of
history or historiography, people tend to assume I must be some kind of theist
apologist (which doesn't follow at all, but this happens all the time anyway).
After 30+ years of observing and taking part in debates
about history with many of my fellow atheists I can safely claim that most
atheists are historically illiterate.
This is not particular to atheists:
they tend to be about as historically illiterate as most people, since
historical illiteracy is pretty much the norm.
But it does mean that when most (not all) atheists comment about history
or, worse, try to use history in debates about religion, they are usually doing
so with a grasp of the subject that is stunted at about high school level.
This is hardly surprising, given that most people don't
study history past high school. But it
means their understanding of any given historical person, subject or event is
(like that of most people), based on half-remembered school lessons, perhaps a
TV documentary or two and popular culture: mainly novels and movies. Which is why most atheists (like most people)
have a grasp of history which is, to be brutally frank, largely crap.
Worse, this also means that most atheists (again, like most
people) have a grasp of how history is studied and the techniques of historical
analysis and synthesis which is also stunted at high school level - i.e.
virtually non-existent. With a few
laudable exceptions, high school history teachers still tend to reduce history
to facts and dates organised into themes or broad topics. How we can know what happened in the past,
with what degree of certitude we can know it and the techniques used to arrive
at these conclusions are rarely more than touched on at this level. This means that when the average atheist (yet
again, like the average person generally) grasps that our knowledge of the past
is not as cut and dried and clear as Mr Wilkins the history teacher gave us to
understand, they tend to reject the whole thing as highly uncertain at best or
subjective waffle at worst. Or, as
Grundy put it, as "crap".
This rejection can be more pronounced in atheists, because
many (not all) come to their atheism via a study of science. Science seems very certain compared to
history. You can make hypotheses and
test them in science. You can actually prove
things. Scientific propositions are, by
definition, falsifiable. Compared to
science, history can seem like so much hand-waving, where anyone can pretty
much argue anything they like.
History and Science
In fact, history is very much a rigorous academic
discipline, with its own rules and methodology much like the hard
sciences. This does not mean it is
a science. It is sometimes referred to
as one, especially in Europe, but this is only in the broader sense of the
word; as in "a systematic way of ordering and analysing
knowledge". But before looking at
how the historical method works, it might be useful to look at how sciences
differ from it.
The hard sciences are founded on the principle of
probabilistic induction. A scientist
uses an inductive or "bottom up" approach to work from observing
specific particulars ("mice injected with this drug put on less fat")
to general propositions ("the drug is reducing their appetite"). These propositions are falsifiable via
empirical testing to rule out other explanations of the particulars ("the
drug is increasing their metabolism" or "those mice are more stressed
by being stuck with syringes") and so can be tested.
This is all possible in the hard sciences because of some
well-established laws of cause and effect that form a basis for this kind of
induction. If something is affecting the
mice in my examples above today, it will affect them in the same way tomorrow,
all things being equal. This allows a
scientist to work from induction to make an assessment of probable causation
via empirical assessment and do so with a high degree of confidence. And their assessment can be confirmed by
others because the empirical measures are controlled and repeatable.
Unfortunately, none of this works for the study of the
past. Events, large and small, occur and
then are gone. A historian can only
assess information about them from traces they may, if we are lucky, leave
behind. But unlike a researcher from the
hard sciences, a historian can't run the fall of the Western Roman Empire
through a series of controlled lab experiments.
He can't even observe the events, as a zoologist might observe the
behaviour of a gorilla band, and draw conclusions. And there aren't well-defined laws and
principles at work (apart from in a very broad and subjective sense) that allow
him to, say, simulate the effects of the rise of the printing press or decide
on the exact course of the downfall of Napoleon the way a theoretical physicist
can with the composition of a distant galaxy or the formation of a long dead
star.
All this leads some atheists, who have fallen in to the
fallacy of scientism and reject anything that can't be definitively
"proven", to reject the idea of any degree of certainty about the
past. This is an extreme position and
it's rarely a consistent one. As I've
noted to some who have claimed this level of historical scepticism, I find it
hard to believe they maintain this position when they read the newspaper, even
though they should be just as sceptical about being able to know about a car
accident yesterday as they are about knowing about a revolution 400 years ago.
The Historical Method
Just because history is not a hard science does not mean it
can't tell us about the past or can't do so with a degree of certainty. Early historians like Herodotus established
the beginnings of the methods used by modern historical researchers, though
historians only began to develop a systematic methodology based on agreed principles
from the later eighteenth century onwards, using the techniques of Barthold Niebuhr (1776-1831) and Leopold von Ranke (1795-1886).
The Historical Method is based on three fundamental steps,
each of which has its own techniques:
1. Heuristic - This is the identification of
relevant material to use as sources of information. These can range from the obvious, such as a
historian of the time's account of events he witnessed personally, to the much
less obvious, like a medieval manor's account book detailing purchases for the
estate. Everything from archaeological
finds to coins to heraldry can be relevant here. The key word here is "relevant",
and there is a high degree of skill in working out which sources of information
are pertinent to the subject in question.
2. Criticism - This is the process of
appraisal of the source material in the light of the question being answered or
subject being examined. It involves such
things as determining the level of "authenticity" of a source (Is it
what is seems to be?), its "integrity" (Can its account be
trusted? What are its biases?), its
context (What genre is it? Is it
responding or reacting to another source?
Is it using literary tropes that need to be treated with
scepticism?) Material evidence, such are
archaeology, architecture, art , coins etc needs to be firmly put into context
to be understood. Documentary sources
also need careful contextualisation - the social conditions of their
production, their polemical intent (if any), their reason for production (more
important for a political speech than a birth certificate, for example) , their
intended audience and the background and biases of their writer (if known) all
have to be taken into account.
3. Synthesis
and Exposition - This is the formal statement of the findings from
steps 1 and 2, which each finding supported by reference to the relevant
evidence.
The main difference between this method and those used in the
hard sciences is that the researcher lays all this material, its analysis and
his conclusions out systematically, but the conclusions are a subjective
assessment of likelihood rather than an objective statement of probabilistic
induction. This subjectivity is what
many trained in the sciences find alien about history and lead them to reject
history as insubstantial.
But the key thing to understand here is that the historian
is not working toward an absolute statement about what definitely happened in
the past, since that is generally impossible except on trivial points (eg there
is no doubt that Adolf HItler was born on April 20 1889). A historian instead works to present what is
called "the argument to the best explanation". In other words, the argument that best
accounts for the largest amount of relevant evidence with the least number of
suppositions. This means that the
Principle of Parsimony, also known as Occam's Razor, is a key tool in
historical analysis; historians always favour the most parsimonious interpretation
that takes account of the most available evidence.
For example, regarding the existence of Jesus, it is far
more parsimonious to conclude that Christianity's figure of "Jesus Christ" evolved
out of the ideas of the followers of a historical Jewish preacher, since all of
our earliest information tells us that this "Jesus Christ" was a
historical Jewish preacher who had been executed circa 30 CE. People have tried to propose alternative
origins for the figure of "Jesus Christ", positing an earlier Jewish
sect that believed in a purely celestial figure who became
"historicised" into an earthly, historical Jesus later. But there is no evidence of any such
proto-Christian sect and no reason such a sect would exist and then vanish
without leaving any trace in the historical record. This is why historians find these "Jesus
Myth" hypotheses uncompelling - they are not the most parsimonious way of
looking at the evidence and require us to imagine ad hoc, "what
if" style suppositions to keep them from collapsing.
Ways Atheists (Sometimes) Get History Wrong
Managing this process of systematic historical analysis
requires training, practice and a degree of skill. Without these, it's very easy to do something
that looks a bit like historical analysis and arrive at flawed conclusions.
Take the initial heuristic process, for example. I've come across many atheists who don't
accept that a historical Jesus existed on the grounds that "there are no
contemporary references to him and all references to him are later
hearsay" or even that "there are no eyewitness accounts of his
career". So they rule out any
evidence we do have referring to him on the basis that it is not contemporary
and/or from eyewitnesses. But if we
ruled out any reference to an ancient, medieval or pre-modern person or event on
these grounds, we'd effectively have to abandon the study of early history: we
don't have contemporary evidence for most people and events in the ancient
world, so this would make almost all of our sources invalid, which is clearly
absurd. Given that we have no eyewitness
or contemporary sources for far more prominent figures, such as Hannibal,
expecting them for a peasant preacher like Jesus is clearly ridiculous. No historian of the ancient world would
regard this as a valid historical heuristic.
Atheists can often make similar elementary errors in the
criticism of sources as well. There is
no shortage of lurid material on the horrors of the Inquisition, with whole
books detailing vile tortures and giving accounts of hundreds of thousands of
wretched victims being consigned to the flames by the Catholic Church. In the past, nineteenth century writers took
these sources at face value and until the early twentieth century this was
essentially the story of the Inquisition to be found in textbooks, especially
in the English-speaking (i.e. substantially Protestant) sphere.
But much of this was based on sources that had severe biases
- mainly sixteenth and seventeenth century Protestant polemical material,
usually produced in England which, as a political, religious and economic enemy
of Spain, was hardly going to produce unbiased accounts of the Spanish church
and crown's use of the Inquisition.
Uncritical use of this material gives a warped, enemy's-eye-view of the
Inquisition that has been substantially overturned by more careful analysis of
the source material and the Inquisition's own records. The result is that it is now known that in
the 160 years of its operation in Spain, the Inquisition resulted in
3,000-5,000 executions, not the hundreds of thousands alleged by uncritical
nineteenth century writers like Henry Charles Lea. Basing an argument on the earlier, uncritical
accounts of the Inquisition might suit many atheists' agendas, but it would be
bad history nonetheless.
Finally, historical synthesis and exposition requires at
least an attempt at a high degree of objectivity. An analyst of the past may have personal
beliefs with the potential to bias their analysis and incline them towards
certain conclusions. Worse, these
beliefs could make them begin with assumptions about the past and so make them
select only the evidence that supports this a priori idea. Historians strive to avoid both and examine
the evidence on its merits, though polemicists often don't bother with this
objective approach. All too often many
atheists can be polemicists when dealing with the past, only crediting
information or analysis that fits an argument against religion they are trying
to make while downplaying, dismissing or
ignoring evidence or analysis that does not fit their agenda. Again, this is bad history and rarely serves
any function other than preaching to the converted.
So, for example, until the early twentieth century the
history of science was popularly seen as a centuries-long conflict between
forward thinking scientific minds trying to advance knowledge and human
progress but constantly being persecuted and suppressed by retrograde religious
forces determined to retard scientific progress. Again, in the mid-twentieth century
historians of science reassessed this general idea and rejected what is now
referred to as the "Conflict Thesis", presenting a far more complex,
nuanced and well-founded analysis of the development of science that shows that
while there were occasional conflicts, which were rarely as simple as
"science versus religion", religion was usually neutral on the
rational analysis of the physical world and often actively supportive of
it. Overt conflicts, such as the Galileo
Affair, were exceptions rather than the rule and, in that case as in many others,
more complicated than simply “religion” repressing “science”.
Objectivity, Bias and Historical Fables
We atheists and freethinkers regularly deride believers for
their irrational thinking, lack of critical analysis and tendency to cling to
ideas out of faith even when confronted by contrary evidence. Unfortunately, it’s a lot easier to talk
about being rational, and criticise others for not being so, than it is to
practice what we preach. Everyone has
their biases and “confirmation bias” -
the tendency to favour information that confirms our prior beliefs - is an
innate psychological propensity that is hard to counter even when we are aware
of it. This means that atheists can, in
many cases, be as bad as believers in accepting appealing ideas without
checking their facts, holding to common misconceptions in the face of contrary
evidence and liking neat, simple stories over messy, complex and more detailed
alternatives that happen to be more solidly supported by the evidence.
The idea that the medieval Church taught the earth was flat,
that Columbus bravely defied their primitive Biblical superstition and proved
they were wrong by sailing to America is a great story. Unfortunately, it’s historical nonsense – a fable
with zero basis in reality. It’s bad
enough that I have had the experience of
intelligent and educated atheists repeating this story as an example of the
Church holding back progress without bothering to check if it’s true. What’s worse is that I’ve also experienced
atheists who have been shown extensive, clear evidence that the medieval Church
taught the earth was round and that the myth of medieval Flat Earth belief was
invented by the novelist Washington Irving in 1828, and they have simply
refused to believe that the myth could be wrong.
Neat historical fables such as the ones about Christians
burning down the Great Library of Alexandria (they didn’t) or murdering Hypatia
because of their hatred of her learning and science (ditto) are appealing
parables. Which means some atheists fight
tooth and nail to preserve them even when confronted with clear evidence that
they are pseudo historical fairy tales.
Fundamentalists aren’t the only ones who can be dogmatic about their
myths.